Marriage Amendment/Same
Sex Marriage
Will Same-Sex Marriage
Lead to Polygamy?
by Dr. R. Albert Mohler Jr.
April 14, 2004
Will
legalization of same-sex marriage lead to the legalization of polygamy?
Proponents of same-sex marriage dismiss the question, for if they
ever did face it squarely, they would have to admit the truly radical
nature of the case for homosexual marriage. The logic of the polygamy
question is this--If marriage can now be homosexual as well as heterosexual,
why must it be limited to two persons rather than three . . . or
several? Proponents of same-sex marriages have dismissed this question
as irresponsible, irrelevant, and inflammatory. The question is
indeed controversial, but only because it demands to be answered.
It is by no means irrelevant.
That fact is underlined by Richard A. Posner in
a recent article published in The New Republic. Posner is a judge
sitting on the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit,
and he also serves as senior lecturer at the University of Chicago
Law School. He is one of the nation's most prolific and influential
legal scholars, and his opinion on this question cannot be dismissed
lightly.
Furthermore, Posner is, generally speaking, a supporter
of same-sex marriage. A legal pragmatist, he suggests that the nation
should experiment with same-sex marriage in order to see if the
legalization of homosexual relationships "works." Posner
accuses the legal advocates of same-sex marriage of ignoring the
clear implications of their own argument.
Posner's analysis comes in the context of his review
of Evan Gerstmann's new book, Same-Sex Marriage and the Constitution.
Gerstmann is no lightweight. His book is considerable both in size
and in influence. Published by Cambridge University Press, it carries
academic clout as well.
Posner criticizes Gerstmann for basing his case
for same-sex marriage on the argument that marriage is a "fundamental
right." Such rights cannot be taken away by the state without
a compelling reason, and Gerstmann argues that the state does not
have any compelling reason to deny same-sex couples the rights of
marriage. As Posner explains, "When Gerstmann describes the
right to marry as fundamental, he means that any person who wants
a marriage license has a strong presumptive right to it regardless
of how the person defines marriage." When applied to same-sex
marriage, this appears to bolster Gerstmann's case. If marriage
is indeed a "fundamental right," the state must offer
a compelling argument against the right of homosexuals to marry,
and Gerstmann alleges that the government has made no such case.
Posner then leaps upon the great legal crevice created
by Gerstmann's argument. When Gerstmann argues that marriage is
a fundamental right, asserting that same-sex couples cannot be denied
this right, Posner understands this logic to go far beyond Gerstmann's
argument. Once marriage is defined as a fundamental right, all persons
must be granted that right unless the state offers a genuinely compelling
argument that would support its denial. As Posner argues, "He
might be a man who wanted to marry his sister (both being sterile),
or a very mature twelve-year-old boy (say, a freshman at MIT) who
wanted to marry his twelve-year-old girlfriend (say, a freshman
at Harvard), or a married man who wanted additional wives so that
they might help out his current wife around the house, or a busy
professional woman who wanted two husbands, the better to take care
of the house and the kids, or a homosexual male who wanted three
male spouses." If marriage is a fundamental right, Posner explains,
then it is a fundamental right for everyone--not only for heterosexual
and homosexual couples.
"If the right to marry, irrespective of the
conventional limitations on number, object, and so on, is fundamental
in the portentous sense of putting on the state the burden of showing
that the recognition of the right in the particular case would work
some serious social harm," Posner instructs, "then it
is doubtful that a marriage license could be refused in any of the
cases that I have described. For what harm does polygamy do, exactly,
and what harm does incest do when there is no possibility of children?
Gerstmann's approach thus has implications far beyond the question
of homosexual marriage as it is ordinarily understood."
Gerstmann is at least partially aware of the problem,
Posner asserts, but he cannot resolve it. "When he attempts
to distinguish polygamy from homosexual marriage by saying that
denying a right to marry several women does not deny the right to
marry the person of your choice, he overlooks the fact that woman
who would like to be a polygamist's second wife is denied the right
to marry the person of her choice." In addressing this question,
Gerstmann argues that if a man were allowed to have two wives, "There
could be no objection to his being allowed to have a thousand wives."
Posner affirms that Gerstmann is here correct--but makes the very
point he seeks to deny. If marriage is claimed as a fundamental
right, it is a right that cannot be taken away from any proposed
marital arrangement that cannot be proved to bring social harm.
This argument is not just a matter of legal technicalities.
This is no inconsequential debate between ivory tower academics.
The question is a matter of serious and consequential legal and
moral significance. Posner, who is no friend of traditional marriage,
at least in his legal reasoning, understands that Gerstmann's argument
in favor of marriage as a fundamental right would lead to a complete
breakdown of the whole structure of laws regulating marriage and
human relationships. Gerstmann, according to Posner, simply will
not see the obvious implications of his own argument. Since the
American people would almost surely reject same-sex marriage by
a landslide if this point were understood, Gerstmann obviously hides
the implications of his own argument from his reader--and perhaps
even from himself.
Gerstmann argues that incestuous marriages (even
when the partners are sterile) should be denied legal status because
this could lead to the exploitation of children. Posner allows that
this is indeed a reason for forbidding a father to marry his daughter,
but the argument does not hold water if it is extended to forbidding
a marriage between siblings, he says. Gerstmann's approach opens
the door for an endless array of contested questions about potential
patterns of intimate relations. Posner comments: "It is a strange
implication of Gerstmann's approach that if a man wanted to marry
his sterile sister, his eighty-year-old grandmother, three other
women, two men, and his Chihuahua, a court would have to turn summersaults
to come up with a 'compelling state interest' that would forbid
these matches."
Posner's article is helpful as it destroys Gerstmann's
legal thesis with devastating power. At the same time, Posner's
own position is grossly inadequate. He sets the standard of "compelling
state interest" so high that no argument is likely to determine
that status. He seems to allow that same-sex marriage would certainly
be legalized if marriage is recognized as a fundamental right. Actually,
the deleterious and disastrous results of displacing and destroying
heterosexual marriage as the centerpiece of human civilization should
be without question a "compelling state interest." Defenders
of traditional marriage can point to a general pattern of social
breakdown, inevitable trauma to children, an innumerable other social
ills in order to make this case. The fact that Posner is not willing
to make the case does no mean that the case cannot be made.
At the same time, we are in Posner's debt for his
incisive critique of Gerstmann's argument--an argument that has
become the mainstay of the homosexual movement. We should also note
Posner's analysis of recent court decision on the issue of homosexuality,
especially the Lawrence v. Texas decision handed down last year
by the U.S. Supreme Court. In nullifying sodomy laws and declaring
a basic right to homosexual practices, the Supreme Court unabashedly
engaged in social engineering. Posner sees no alternative to this,
and calls upon jurists to be honest that this is exactly what they
are doing.
"Judges like to pretend that their decisions
are dictated by 'logic,' or by an authoritative text or precedent,"
Posner explains, "because it downplays the element of judicial
discretion, which worries people." According to Posner, "The
pretense wears particularly thin in constitutional cases about marriage
and sex, because the Constitution does not say anything about these
subjects, and the framers of the Constitution, and of the major
amendments, in particular the Fourteenth Amendment, which is the
principal source of constitutional rights against the states, were
not thinking about marriage, sex, homosexuality, or related topics
when they drafted these founding documents."
That assessment is profoundly accurate, and Posner
simply explains that the Supreme Court's decisions in sex-related
matters (including Roe v. Wade) are all "political" decisions,
in the sense that they are "motivated by values not dictated
by the orthodoxed materials of judicial decision-making." As
Posner admits, "Precedent and analogy operate as fig leaves
in such cases."
A fig leaf serves as a good description of the legal
rational behind the U.S. Supreme Court's decisions in so many matters
related to human sexuality and the sanctity of human life. Eagerly
engaged in social engineering, justices have claimed a legal basis
for their arguments, but Posner sees through this pretense and calls
upon judges to admit that they are doing politics form the bench.
Defenders of traditional marriage would do
well to pay attention to Judge Richard Posner's analysis. His explanation
of fig leaves and fundamental rights is both incisive and important--and
his status as a legal scholar cannot be discounted. If marriage
no longer means uniting a man and a woman, it can mean virtually
anything--and will.
|